In this post, Branko Milanovic, Senior Scholar at the Stone Center on Socio-Economic Inequality at CUNY and Visiting Professor at the LSE’s International Inequalities Institute, steps back to address the fundamental question: why should we care about the level of inequality in society? Why does inequality matter when it comes to the outlook for economic growth, for reasons of fairness, and for the functioning of the political system?
This is the question that I am often asked – so I decided to write my answers down…
The argument why inequality should not matter is almost always couched in the following way: if everybody is getting better-off, why should we care if somebody is becoming extremely rich? Perhaps he deserves to be rich – or whatever the case, even if he does not deserve it, we need not worry about his wealth. If we do, that implies envy and other moral flaws. I have dealt with the misplaced issue of envy here (in response to points made by Martin Feldstein) and here (in response to Harry Frankfurt), and do not want to repeat it. So, let’s leave envy out and focus on the reasons why we should be concerned about high inequality.
The reasons can be formally broken down into three groups: instrumental reasons having to do with economic growth, reasons of fairness, and reasons of politics.
The relationship between inequality and economic growth is one of the oldest relationships studied by economists. A very strong presumption was that without high profits there will be no growth, and high profits imply substantial inequality. We find this argument already in Ricardo where profit is the engine of economic growth. We find it also in Keynes and Schumpeter, and then in standard models of economic growth. We find it even in Stalinist industrialization debates. To invest you have to have profits (that is, surplus above subsistence); in a privately-owned economy it means that some people have to be wealthy enough to save and invest, and in a state-directed economy, it means that the state should take all the surplus.
A strong presumption was that without high profits there will be no growth, and high profits imply substantial inequality.
But notice that throughout the argument is not one in favour of inequality as such. If it were, we would not be concerned about the use of the surplus. The argument is about a seemingly paradoxical behaviour of the wealthy: they should be sufficiently rich but should not use that money to live well and consume, but rather to invest. This point is quite nicely, and famously, made by Keynes in the opening paragraphs of his book, The Economic Consequence of the Peace. For us, it is sufficient to note that this is an argument in favour of inequality provided wealth is not used for private pleasure.
The empirical work conducted over the past twenty years has failed to uncover a positive relationship between inequality and growth. The data were not sufficiently good, especially regarding inequality where the typical measure used was the Gini coefficient which is too aggregate and inert to capture changes in the distribution; also the relationship itself may vary as a function of other variables, or the level of development. This has led economists to a cul-de-sac and discouragement – so much so that since the late 1990s and early 2000s such empirical literature has almost ceased to be produced. It is reviewed in more detail in Section 2 of this paper.
More recently, with much better data on income distribution, the argument that inequality and growth are negatively correlated has gained ground. In a joint paper Roy van der Weide and I show this using forty years of US micro data. With better data and somewhat more sophisticated thinking about inequality, the argument becomes much more nuanced: inequality may be good for future incomes of the rich (that is, they become even richer) but it may be bad for future incomes of the poor (that is, they fall further behind). In this dynamic framework, the growth rate itself is no longer something homogeneous as indeed it is not in real life. When we say that the American economy is growing at 3% per year, it simply means that the person with the average income is getting better off at that rate; it tells us nothing about how much better off, or worse off, others are getting.
Why would inequality have a bad effect on the growth of the lower deciles of the distribution as Roy and I find? Because it leads to low educational (and even health) achievements among the poor who become excluded from meaningful jobs and from meaningful contributions they could make to their own and society’s improvement. Excluding a certain group of people from good education, be it because of their insufficient income or gender or race, can never be good for the economy, or at least it can never be preferable to their inclusion.
Excluding a certain group of people from good education, be it because of their insufficient income or gender or race, can never be good for the economy
High inequality, which effectively debars some people from full participation, translates into an issue of fairness or justice. It does so because it affects intergenerational mobility. People who are relatively poor (which is what high inequality means) are not able, even if they are not poor in an absolute sense, to provide for their children a fraction of the benefits – from education and inheritance to social capital – that the rich provide to their offspring. This implies that inequality tends to persist across generations which in turn means that opportunities are vastly different for those at the top of the pyramid and those on the bottom. We have the two factors joining forces here: on the one hand, the negative effect of exclusion on growth that carries over generations (which is our instrumental reason for not liking high inequality), and on the other, lack of equality of opportunity (which is an issue of justice).
High inequality has also political effects. The rich have more political power and they use that political power to promote their own interests and to entrench their relative position in society. This means that all the negative effects due to exclusion and lack of equality of opportunity are reinforced and made permanent (at least, until a big social earthquake destroys them). In order to fight off the advent of such an earthquake, the rich must make themselves safe and unassailable from “conquest”. This leads to adversarial politics and destroys social cohesion. Ironically, the social instability which then results discourages investments of the rich, that is it undermines the very action that was at the beginning adduced as the key reason why high wealth and inequality may be socially desirable.
The rich have more political power and they use that political power to promote their own interests and to entrench their relative position in society
We therefore reach the end point where the unfolding of actions that were at first supposed to produce beneficent outcomes destroy by their own logic the original rationale. We have to go back to the beginning and instead of seeing high wealth as promoting investments and growth, we begin to see it, over time, as producing exactly the opposite effects: reducing investments and growth.
This post was originally published on the author’s Substack in May 2021.
Sign up here for a monthly newsletter summary of LSE Inequalities blog posts.
All articles posted on this blog give the views of the author(s). They do not represent the position of LSE Inequalities, nor of the London School of Economics and Political Science.
Image credit: The Road Provides via Shutterstock.