LSE - Small Logo
LSE - Small Logo

Blog Admin

March 7th, 2014

Scotland could end up as a kind of post-sovereign polity in a looser union with England

0 comments

Estimated reading time: 5 minutes

Blog Admin

March 7th, 2014

Scotland could end up as a kind of post-sovereign polity in a looser union with England

0 comments

Estimated reading time: 5 minutes

Michael KeatingOur politicians are still clinging to antiquated notions of sovereignty, argues Michael Keating. While British governments have in recent decades come to accept the idea of Scottish self-determination, they have not been able to see their way beyond traditional ideas of sovereignty, so that Scotland must be subordinate to Westminster or completely independent. The moderate solution to the problem is rejected while the extreme one is reluctantly accepted. It is not necessary to become an independent state in order to forge a distinct welfare settlement but a new division of competences would be required.

There are several ironies in the current constitutional debate in Scotland. One is that both sides are talking the language of union. The label ‘unionist’, previously a highly charged term associated with the Conservative and Unionist Party and loaded with Irish implications, has been embraced by all UK parties, including Labour and (with the occasional qualification) Liberal Democrats. On the nationalist side, Alex Salmond has argued that there are six unions, of which an independent Scotland would keep five (currency, monarchy, society, Europe and defence). Another irony is that, while the Edinburgh agreement and the referendum question excludes ‘third way’ options such as ‘devolution max’, both sides are seeking to position themselves in that very middle ground in the knowledge that occupying it is the key to victory.

Post-Sovereignty

This is not mere political posturing but reflects a profound truth about modern constitutionalism, that the old sovereign nation-state formula no longer works. We are in an era of ‘post-sovereignty’. This does not mean that sovereignty has disappeared but that in its traditional monist form it is no longer the only principle of political order.

More profoundly, sovereignty as a principle is in question. At the supranational level, the European Union has become a legal order in its own right and, within its domain, its laws trump national ones. The only redress to this, recognized in the Lisbon Treaty, is secession – but that option is also open to Scotland within the United Kingdom. Indeed the principle of state sovereignty is also in question domestically. Arguments that the Scottish Parliament is the creation of Westminster, which could abolish it tomorrow, carry little political credibility. Moreover, the issue of sovereignty has never been resolved in Scotland, where Blackstone and Dicey’s ideas have never commanded consensus. The existence of the Scottish Parliament focuses this alternative idea of where sovereignty might lie. Hence there are, and always have been, two interpretations of the union: as the incorporation of Scotland into a sovereign and unitary state; and as a bargain that can be revisited from time to time by either party. Similar arguments exist in Spain and in Canada, although their legal basis is perhaps less developed.

In such states, it is futile to seek a single foundational principle to underlie constitutional order and define sovereignty. The endless Canada/Quebec search for a settlement and the current constitutional deadlock between the majorities in Catalonia and Spain show this. The only option is a constitutional pluralism that does not seek to dig down to the foundations all the time but recognizes differences in constitutional traditions and aspirations. The Northern Ireland settlement is a rare example of two states accepting this idea. In recent decades, British governments have come to accept the idea of Scottish self-determination, in a way they did not a hundred years ago in the case of Ireland. John Major, Margaret Thatcher and now David Cameron have reinterpreted the union in this way. On the other hand, they have not been able to see their way beyond traditional ideas of sovereignty, so that Scotland must be subordinate to Westminster or completely independent. So the moderate solution to the problem is rejected while the extreme one is reluctantly accepted. Canada and Spain have similarly missed out on opportunities in the Meech Lake Accord and the revised Catalan Statute of Autonomy because they could not accept even the hint of divided sovereignty.

Opinion polls in Scotland have regularly shown a large section of the population (usually a plurality) in favour of extended devolution within the United Kingdom. Since this is almost everyone else’s second option, it would seem to be the basis for achieving the widest degree of consensus (based on necessary compromise if not shared premises). It is true that there is some confusion over exactly what people do want and how much variation in policy they would accept across the United Kingdom, but there seems little appetite for a separate military effort or formal status within the United Nations. On the other hand, there is support for more control over taxation and welfare, the big items of domestic policy not already devolved. This is not surprising. Both economic and welfare policy are rescaling upwards and downwards in Europe so that the nation-state is not the sole level for either or for the social compromises that they embody. This is as true of a potentially independent Scotland as it is for the United Kingdom.

Implications for Scotland

Scots do not differ radically from citizens elsewhere in the United Kingdom in their broad preferences for welfare. Public policy, however, does not emerge directly from citizen preferences but from the aggregation and compromise among interests and preferences within political institutions. This has produced a rather different balance within Scotland, notably on matters of universalism and public provision. In the longer run such differences necessarily imply distinct fiscal choices, and indicate the need for mechanisms by which Scotland might recapture the benefits of its own social investments, for example in university education. It also points to changes in the balance of welfare instruments so as to fit local needs and preferences. Measures like the ‘bedroom tax/spare room subsidy’, designed for conditions in the south of England, may have little relevance in Scotland (or in the north of England for that matter).

As a matter of functional efficiency, the present division between passive welfare (reserved) and active welfare (largely devolved) creates mismatches and disincentives, which are beginning to be recognized. The location of housing benefit at the same level as responsibility for social housing is one instance. Another matter is the interface among unemployment support and disability support with training, economic development, urban regeneration and social work services. There is never an undisputed optimal level for the integration of public services and the idea of ‘joined-up government’ is often a naïve illusion, but we can probably do a lot better than at present.

It is fruitless to design a reformed system of devolution predicated on the present mode of welfare state. One thing that we do know is that the welfare state is going to undergo some major changes, if only for pressing financial reasons. This provides an opportunity to rethink how Scottish welfare might fit into an emerging multilevel model and how resources might most effectively be deployed.

It is not necessary to become an independent state in order to forge a distinct welfare settlement but a new division of competences would be required. The nearest comparator would be the province of Quebec which, after repeated efforts to arrive at a constitutional settlement, has engaged in the building of a distinct polity within the Canadian federation and use its extensive taxation and welfare responsibilities to forge a distinct welfare settlement, not radically different from that elsewhere in Canada but sufficiently distinct to have made a real difference in outcomes. In the numerous meetings I attend in Scotland on the constitutional issue, it is these social and economic issues that feature most prominently.

It is my belief that Scotland will end up as a kind of post-sovereign polity in a looser union with England and forging its own social compromises within the constraints of markets and wider unions. Our politicians, however, will take us there while denying strenuously that this is what they are doing, and still clinging to antiquated notions of sovereignty.

Note: This article was originally published on the PSA’s Insight blog and gives the views of the author, and not the position of the British Politics and Policy blog, nor of the London School of Economics. Please read our comments policy before posting. Image: Scottish Parliament ajnabee CC BY 2.0

About the Author

Michael KeatingMichael Keating is Professor of Politics, Universities of Aberdeen and Edinburgh and Director of ERC Scottish Centre on Constitutional Change. He will be speaking further on this issue at an event organised by the British Academy on Wednesday 5 March.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

About the author

Blog Admin

Posted In: Scotland Independence Referendum

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *